Unsatisfactory introductions

Spread the love

I have  been perplexed over the years by the number of times that I have read and heard views attributed to Popper which don’t sound quite the same as the ideas of the man himself,  at least as I understood him.

This prompted some questions about what was being taught to undergraduates and in 1989 I surveyed the undergraduate courses and reading lists in Philosophy, Politics and Sociology in the (then) 21 Australian universities. The objective was to find what they were being told about Popper and Hayek who I regarded as the twin pillars of anti-scientism and classical liberalism. (That was before I discovered Mises. Due to Popper’s favourable references to Hayek I explored the books of  latter but did not find in Hayek the kind of references to Mises that would have prompted me to pursue his books.) Getting back to my survey, the short answer is that you had to be very lucky to get more than a passing reference to Popper and the situation with Hayek was worse.Round about 1998 I wanted to repeat the survey but there were more than 50 universities thanks to the rebadging of a heap of  colleges which used to award diplomas in teaching, arts and crafts, rural studies etc. So instead I searched over 200 websites of philosophy schools, mostly in the US but also a few others like Cambridge. The story was the same, Popper rated a mention in the philosophy of science but only as a preliminary to Kuhn, Lakatos, Feyerabend and the sociology of science. No indication that his contribution was more robust or extended into other fields where he did first order work – evolutionary epistemology, logic and probabililty theory, metaphysics, philosophy of mind, history of ideas, politics and the social sciences.

In recent years some writers have emerged with a strong line of philosophy books for layfolk – the names that come to mind include Grayling, Blackburn and de Botton, with others who have been less prolific. I can’t afford to accumulate many more books (apart from the cost there is no room in the house) so I have mostly checked in the bookshops, not the ideal place to do research, but the impression is that Popper  might get a para and a footnote, or maybe even a couple of pages, half devoted to the failure of falsificationism. This is weird because I never thought that “falsificationist” was an appropriate label for Popperism, that is just the most obvious point of difference from the positivists.

The issue came to a head recently when I was sucked into a prolonged debate with a positivist on an Austrian economcs blog. Only one other person on the site was on my side of the debate, despite the fairly elementary mistakes in Popper exegesis that were put on display, with a liberal amount of sleazy ad hominems about Popper and Popperians.

So again I wondered about the contents of introductory books on philosophy and promptly borrowed ten or a dozen from the local public library for systematic study. Some of these books are written for popular consumption, some are written to support uni courses. They are all written by academics and they are published by reputable presses.

All that I have examined so far present a more or less distorted account of Popper’s ideas. Some of the errors are repeated, almost word for word, suggesting that there is some primary source that they are drawing on  (not yet identified because they don’t tend to quote with citations, they just have reading lists at the end of the book or the chapter).

Starting with the most up  market, written to support the undergrad courses at the University of London.  It is edited by A C Grayling, titled “Philosophy 1: A Guide Through the Subject”, OUP, 1998

Preface  “The essays, although introductory, are not elementary, because they are aimed at those who wish to take a more than superficial look at philosophy. They therefore seek to give the full character of inquiry into its most important questions”.

The volume started as a project to commission material to accompany undergraduate courses in philosophy at the Uni of London.

“London has arguably one of the best single-subject degrees in philosophy offered by any university in the world. When the opportunity arose to put together a collection of essays to serve as a companion to London’s philosophy degree, the missionary possibility immediatey suggested itself of promoting the university’s conception of what is central to philosophical study. This volume is the result”.

The book “…is also a survey: anyone interested to know what is at the centre of each major area of philosophical inquiry will find these essays thoroughly informative”.

The book attracted a number of rave reviews on Amazon.

The articles are largely bereft of Continental mambo-jumbo, and refreshingly competent across the board; therefore, the two volumes may serve as a major reference work on any shelf, as well as an apt introduction and stimulation for serious college students.

“Philosophy 1” is a good introductory survey text. While it is somewhat more technical than what the casual reader may want, my goal was to learn something about “real philosophy, not simplified philosophy.” The book hit the mark on this account.

This thorough introduction to the core areas of philosophy is written by some of the leading figures in their specialisms, and it is remarkable for its lucidity and comprehensiveness, and for the excellent bibliographies attached to each chapter… Both volumes are outstanding pedagogical collections, and their editor, AC Grayling of London University, has ensured that between them they provide what is perhaps the highest quality pacakge of introduction-to-philosophy literature available anywhere in the world today. I found it especially helpful, in my own studies and in guiding students, to have such full material on all the branches of philosophy available together in the two volumes, because it made for ease of cross-reference, and topics that were mentioned in certain of the chapters were fully explored in others. You could say that the two volumes together are a complete introduction to contemporary analytic philosophy, and there is nothing comparable to them for scope, depth, or clarity in the literature for students and teachers of philosophy now available.

The chapter on Epistemology has an introduction by Grayling which spells out the framework for the topic that pervades the book.

“In the tradition of debate on these matters knowledge is standardly defined as justified true belief, because at the very least it seems that to know something one must believe it, one’s belief must be true, and one’s reason for believing it must be satisfactory in the light of some standard.”

David Papineau wrote Chapter 3 on “Methodology: The elements of the philosophy of science”.

“Logic is the study of deductively valid reasoning…[however]…in both everyday life and in science the arguments we use do not provide conclusive reasons for their conclusions…This discussion of methodology will be concerned with this kind of non-conclusive resoning and with various philosophical issues that arise in trying to understand it. There will be five sections: (1) Induction and its problems; (2) Laws of nature; (3) Realism, instrumentalism and underdetermination; (4) Confirmation and probability; (5) Explanation”.

Moving on to the problem of induction.

“Generally speaking, ‘induction’ refers to any form of inference in which we move from a finite set of observations or experimental results to a conclusion about how things generally behave”. The examples cited are fine weather after a red sky in the evening, and the characteristic colour of sodium when it is heated in a Bunsen flame.

The problem of induction is to determine the reliability of the conclusion (the truth of the law if you like) given (1) the finite set of observations only represents a sample of the whole population of fine days (or red evening skies) and sodium flames and (2) the logical possibility that the law could change.

Papineau noted some of the efforts that have been made to handle the problem; invoking a principle of induction, the inductive argument for induction and introducing probability. He then moved on to Popper.

Popper’s Alternative to Induction

“In Popper’s view, science does not rest on induction in the first place. He denies that scientists start with observations and then infer a general theory. Rather, they put forward a theory…and then compare its predictions with observations to see whether it stands up to test. If such tests prove negative, then the theory is experimentally falsified and the scientists will seek some  new alternative.”

“According to Popper, the inferences which matter to science are refutations…these inferences are not inductive but deductive…The point here is that it is much easier to disprove theories than to prove them. A single contrary example suffices for a conclusive disproof, but no number of supporting examples will constitute a conclusive proof.”

Actually Popper drew a distinction between the logic of testing and the result of testing (falsifiablity vs falsification). In logic a negative is decisive but in practice a failed test is usually not decisive, it just puts a question mark on the theory for further work].

“So according to Popper, science is a sequence of conjectures. Scientific theories are put forward as hypotheses, and they are replaced by new hypotheses when they are falsified. However this view of science raises an obvious question: if scientific theories are always conjectural, then what makes science better than astrology,or spirit worship or any other form of unwarranted superstition? A non-Popperian would answer this question by saying that real science proves its claims on the basis of observational evidence, whereas superstition is nothing but guesswork. But, on Popper’s account, even scientific theories are guesswork – for they cannot be proved by observations, but are themselves  merely undefeated conjectures.”

Some comments before going on to the criticism.

1. Theories are not replaced when they encounter problems, they are usually only replaced by a better theory.

2. Conjectural scientific theories are better than astrology etc because they form systems with wide-ranging explanatory power, articulating with theories in adjacent fields (and in the case of major advances, unifying related fields). They also point the way to further research.

3. Theories may arise as guesses but they need to survive tests to be taken seriously, so the talk of guesswork is a red herring, like David Stove comparing the guesses of scientists with guessing the toss of the coin at the start of a cricket match.

The Failings of Falsificationism 

“The central objection to his account is that it only accounts for negative scientific knowledge, as opposed to positive knowledge..He says nothing about what can show us that a theory is right.”

Popper did say things about selecting the theory that is best, even though he cannot say how to guarantee that it is right (neither can the positivsts!). You favour the theroy that solves the problem (usually explanation and prediction) and stands up to tests as well or better than the others.

“Yet it is positive knowledge of this latter kind that is supposed to follow from inductive inferences. What is more, it is this kind of positive knowledge that makes induction so important.”

How come the inductivists are still working on the problem of induction so they can demonstrate positive knowledge?

“We can cure diseases and send people to the moon because we know that certain causes do always have certain results, not because we know that they don’t. If Popper cannot explain how we sometimes know that ‘All As are Bs”, rather than just ‘It’s false that all As are Bs’, then he has surely failed to deal properly with the problem of induction”.

That comment indicates a move from the logic of induction to the metaphysical theory that there are regularities in the world which enable us to make more or less reliable predictions, using well tested theories inside their zone of application.

“Popper’s usual answer to this objection is that he is concerned with the logic of pure scientific research, not with practical questions about practical applications”.

Popper was equally concerned with practical applications as he indicated in one of his replies to critics in the Shilpp volume (Library of Living Philosophers).

There  is more to be said but that would appear to indicate that the reading of Popper in this potentially very influential book is suspect.

This entry was posted in Uncategorized. Bookmark the permalink.

8 Responses to Unsatisfactory introductions

  1. Brian Scurfield says:

    “The Black Swan” by Nassim Taleb was a recent best seller that makes more than a passing mention of Popper and where Popper is talked about very favourably.

  2. Rafe says:

    Yes in view of Taleb’s high profile my NZ friend in advertising suggested to get a leg up on his reputation by setting up up a site or blog called The Black Swan and point out the Popperian elements of Taleb’s approach.

    Daniel has an Ayn Rand blog, not because he is a fan but he has a long-running debate with a Randian friend of his and this is a vehicle for the discussion. He is a critical rationalist and I think we met in the Critical Cafe, many years ago.

    This is his blog http://aynrandcontrahumannature.blogspot.com/

    He has a partner on the blog and he has been too busy at work to post a lot himself lately.

    And this is his advertising agency. http://www.barnescatmur.com/

  3. Elliot says:

    Godwin scholarship is worse.

    Burke scholarship may be worse too. For Burke, I haven’t read much bad stuff myself, but Connor Cruise O’Brien wrote like 50 pages complaining about it in his extremely good Burke biography. He said it was dominant for a long time and gave examples. I think he was correct, but I don’t know if the current situation after his book is the same, nor can I compare it very well with Popper scholarship.

    Plato scholarship is horrific too as Popper explained in OSE. And anything about the presocratics is unreliable.

    It’s easy to misunderstand living thinkers when we have easy access to all their books, and even when we can ask them questions. The situation is worse with dead people.

    Even people like Brian Magee who knew Popper personally, spent lots of time talking to Popper, and were generally favorably disposed, developed serious misconceptions. It’s similar with most (all?) of Popper’s students and assistants.

    I don’t think anything very special is going on here. I bet many Marxists think Marx is misunderstood. Many Randians consider Rand misunderstood (and, I might add, many Randians misunderstand Rand). I think misunderstandings are the *default outcome*, not something very notable. Communication is hard and error is easy.

    This is why we need critical discussions. The better people understand the content of Popper’s views, the more easily they will be able to correctly interpret what he meant in various passages. And in the general case, criticism helps correct errors, and without it everything always goes wrong.

  4. Of course, Popper would say he didn’t understand all the implications of his own theories either. And Ayn Rand *definitely* didn’t understand a great deal of her own theories – for example, her epistemology is logically compatible, if not identical, with, with her arch enemies, the skeptics. And that’s with a highly charitable interpretation – it could also easily be subjectivist/relativist. That’s why thinkers need critics themselves – they often don’t quite know what it is they write.

  5. Lee Kelly says:

    The degree to which Popper is misrepresented is alarming, considering that the perpretators are so qualified and apparently confident in their views. One would hardly get the impression that these authors had only been exposed to Popper’s ideas by second hand sources, but I iven the extent of their errors I can’t believe it otherwise.

    This is the most disconcerting thing about it all.

    I am reminded of the popular media. Whenever there is a story on something which one has in-depth and intimite knowledge of, the gross errors and ignorance of the reporters is obvious. However,, most people tend to assume this is not the case for the remaining 99% of the stories, which they do not have in-depth and intimate knowledge of.

    Perhaps it was wrong of me to ever expect more of professional academics in the first place. In any case, it worries me, because I think people commit the same mistake with such academic scribblers as they do for “serious” reporters.

  6. Brian Scurfield says:

    I agree with Elliot: nothing special is going on here. Misunderstandings are indeed the default outcome and that is in consequence of the truth not being manifest. For communication to happen, the receiver has to generate conjectures about the content of the communication and to criticise them. This must happen at many levels, from apprehending sounds and words to distilling meaning. The knowledge thereby created is new knowledge within the receiver’s brain and, since the whole process of it’s creation is fallible, it won’t necessarily be isomorphic to the knowledge in the brain of the sender and there is no way for the receiver to be sure it is. Furthermore, and similarly, the sender’s message generation process relies on fallible conjectures and refutations and there is no way for the sender to be sure the conveyed message was the intended one.

    Communication is difficult, that won’t change, but I think that ideas with reach tend to stick around so that gives me optimism that Popper’s ideas will survive.

    @Daniel: You blog title has “human nature” in it: Is there such a thing? Is not that idea contra-Popper?

  7. Elliot says:

    > The degree to which Popper is misrepresented is alarming, considering that the perpretators are so qualified and apparently confident in their views. One would hardly get the impression that these authors had only been exposed to Popper’s ideas by second hand sources, but I iven the extent of their errors I can’t believe it otherwise.

    I disagree on several counts.

    I don’t see that it’s alarming. Is it not commonplace? If we find the common alarming, I think that indicates more about our perspective being mistaken than anything else.

    As to second hand sources, I know that many people have read primary sources and then misunderstood Popper (and I also know this for Rand, Godwin, Burke, and others). I have talked to such people about both what they’ve read and what they understood it to have said. Misunderstanding primary sources is common.

    A great example is with _The Fabric of Reality_ by David Deutsch. This is a good as a primary source for the Popperian issues it covers, and covers some other things. In my estimate, 99% of the its readers (read the actual book, not an article about it) have a correct understanding, in broad outline, of less than 50% of the main issues discussed in the book. And for the Popperian stuff, it’s quite rare that anyone understood it.

    This is simply because the material is very hard (relative to the level of philosophical sophistication (in primarily the sense of ability to approach and understand new philosophy) found in people who are not already Popperians).

    The more familiar ideas are, the better they communicate because the receiver/learner has an easier time figuring out what it all means. The less familiar — as is the case with advanced philosophy like Popper’s, which also happens to strongly contradict a great deal of existing ideas — then the harder it is to learn it.

    Even much, much easier things than Popperian philosophy, such as calculus or trig, are hard to learn. Most readers of calculus books fail to understand calculus. Calculus doesn’t face the challenge of contradicting a lot of stuff everyone thinks they already know. It’s more of a “hard” subject with less vague statements to misunderstand. But it doesn’t matter. People are horrible at teaching almost anything, and people are horrible at learning almost anything (“horrible” relatively to our standards). And why shouldn’t they be? They don’t know anything about epistemology and its implications for education.

    These are the main sources of error, not failure to read primary sources (which certainly happens sometimes too).

  8. Rafe says:

    I think it is alarming that people who are supposed to have a professional interest in the truth have been so cavalier about the truth in the case of Popper.

    So what is new? I take that point, but the case of Popper is special because of the importance of Popper’s ideas and the depth and breadth of his achievement.

    Marxists and Wittgenstinians and positivists and others say that their favorite person is misunderstood but the shelves in bookshops groan under the weight of books about them. Look for the CR books for comparison!

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

please answer (required): * Time limit is exhausted. Please reload the CAPTCHA.